|
|
The
seminar is held in hybrid
format, in person (Múzeum
krt. 4/i Room 224) and
online.
________________________________________________________
|
5
April (Friday) 4:15
PM Room 224 + ONLINE
|
Zoltán
Jakab
|
Institute for the
Psychology of Special
Needs
Eötvös Loránd University,
Budapest
|
|
Mental
files and metarepresentation:
data and theory on the
development of false belief
attribution and intensionality
|
Recent data seem to support the
view that the understanding of
false belief emerges in infancy,
way before fluent speech. A
related question is, when children
come to understand intensionality,
that is, the idea that one and the
same object may be represented in
different ways by different
people. Contrary to false belief,
the latter question is not easily
approached by the methods of
dishabituation and preferential
looking, therefore existing
studies examine young children in
preschool age. One central
question is, does the
understanding of intensionality
constitute a separate stage of
mindreading development that
follows the mastering of explicit,
verbal-response-based false belief
tasks, or as soon as children
succeed in verbal false belief
tasks they have at least an
initial grasp of intensionality.
Empirical results are complex and
controversial on this issue. An
interesting contender in
accounting for them is mental file
theory, which suggests that
children who understand
first-order, but not second-order
false belief can form the required
kinds of mental files, but cannot
yet handle them reliably in every
respect, and this explains their
interestingly faltering
performance on dual-identity
object tasks.
|
|
12
April (Friday) 4:15
PM Room 224 + ONLINE
|
Jeffrey
Strayer
|
Purdue
University Fort Wayne
|
|
Art and
Identity: Nothing, Something,
and Everything
|
|
The history of art suggests that
any artwork of any kind of artwork
is an object of some kind of
object that has been singled out
by the artist whose work it is in
a way that is consistent with the
nature of the object that the work
is intended to be. I have defended
this view in my books Subjects
and Objects and
Haecceities as forming part
of the basis for investigating the
limits of Abstraction in art and
the possibilities of producing
radical works with kinds of
identity whose novelty may test
certain assumptions on which
artworks are thought to rely. This
paper concentrates on a single
language-based work of art that
can be understood to be nothing,
something, or everything
at the same or different times,
thus suggesting that, given the
relation of artistic intention to
the creative determination of
identity, Leibniz’s Law can be
violated with certain works of
art. It is reasonable to suppose
that any artwork, no matter how
radical, is something that results
from at least one intentional
conception that fits the nature of
the thing that is produced
according to that conception. And
the basic conditions of making and
apprehending works of art dictate
that artworks either are, or
depend on, particular objects that
have particular identities that
are determined and grasped
according to certain conceptions.
Given that these things are the
case, one of the more reductive
artworks possible would be something
realized in an event of conception
in which it is understood to
become what it is meant to be in
the act of conceiving of its being
the being that fits the conditions
of its conception. This can be
achieved with directing language
to its understanding in such a way
that what is singled out by the
language understood depends on
conceiving of its relation to a
conception that incorporates
understanding the relation of that
thing to the conceiving of that
conception. The language of the
artwork of this paper includes a
gap that can be mentally filled in
either of two ways, making two
versions of the language. The
first version of the language
enables it to single out something
or everything, depending on how
that version is understood. Since
everything, as an object,
as something, consists of each
thing of every kind of thing,
including abstract, fictional, and
impossible objects as well as
spatio-temporal entities, it would
appear to be impossible to produce
a work of art that is everything
beyond simply declaring a
particular work of art to be
everything. However, there is a
more interesting, productive, and
minimal way of making everything,
as the all-inclusive object, be a
work of art that fits the goal of
producing a reductive object of
radical identity. This can be done
through so understanding the same
language on which the work as
something relies that, in virtue
of its being affected by the
forming of a particular
conception, everything becomes
linked to itself through the
conception on which it depends to
acquire the property of being
linked to itself through the
conceiving of that conception.
Producing a work of art with a
radically reductive identity
depends in part on using
perception and conception as media
or means of producing an object so
linked to an event or events of
conscious conception that it
reflects its relation to the event
on which it depends to have an
identity that exhibits its
connection to that conception. On
one interpretation of the language
of this work, something is
linked to itself through a
reflexive conscious conception
that is monadic and second order,
and on the other interpretation everything,
as the maximum object, is related
to itself through an event of
reflexive conception that is
dyadic and first order. This shows
that the form of an artwork may
not be defined solely by the
settled terms and relations of a
perceptual object, but may be
shaped or determined by the form
of the conception on which it
depends to be one or another
object of conception. In this
case, the form of the same single
work of art can differ according
to whether it is understood to be
something or everything as either
is determined by a particular
conception to be the object of
that conception. In addition,
because of the odd nature of the
object that is everything, an
artwork that is understood to be
everything has a complex form
whose irregularity differs from
the form of any other object of
any other kind of object. The
wording of the second version of
the language of this artwork is
designed to engage its
comprehension so that nothing
is delineated for thought through
thought as that to which something
conceived cannot be related
through the conception of that to
which something conceived cannot
be related through its conception.
As this version of the
specification is understood, its
language is so related to its
understanding that there is an
ensured failure to reach nothing
in the reflexive understanding
that incorporates its defeated
relation to pure nothingness as a
dimension of that understanding.
This enables that version of the
specification to establish one
kind of ultimate radical identity,
since ‘what’ is singled out by the
specification understood must lack
the identity that ‘it’ is
understood ‘it’ cannot be
conceived to have. Here the
conventional object of art, with
its form and content, is displaced
by a conception in which the
notion of object elimination is
reached by language engaging
thought in a way that ends in the
conceptual vacancy that is tied to
that conception. Since nothing is
not an object, and yet can be
understood to be a work of art in
the ways indicated herein,
considerations of the work of art
that is the subject of this paper
show that not every work of art
has a conventional identity that
is associated with a single stable
object, thus raising novel
questions about the relation of
art, mind, objects, and ontology.
|
19
April (Friday) 4:15
PM Room 224 + ONLINE
|
Bence
Marosán
|
Department
of International
Relations, Budapest
Business School
|
|
Phenomenological
and empirical investigations
concerning the genesis and
fundamental nature of minimal
mind
|
Consciousness belongs to the
most important and miraculous
issues of contemporary
philosophical and empirical
scientific research. There are
hundreds (maybe thousands) of
different models that try to
explain the genesis and
fundamental nature of
consciousness, yet, there is no
consensual model today. In this
lecture I would like to provide
a specific branch of such
models, namely, the subcortical
models of consciousness,
according to which certain
neural mechanisms in the
subcortical parts of the brain
(most importantly in
Mesencephalon and Diencephalon)
are responsible for the
emergence of consciousness at
the lowest level. These
mechanisms arose during the
evolution to help the organism
to cope certain environmental
challenges. In this lecture I
would like to offer certain
suggestions, how such models
could be tested and studied in a
phenomenologically legitimate
way, that is to say, in a way
which is directly accessible for
one’s first-person perspective.
I would like to propose certain
experiment which would help us
to test such models, in such a
way which would provide us
direct evidence for the truth of
this approach, (or, just the
opposite way, which would weaken
such claims).
|
|
26
April (Friday) 4:15
PM Room 224 + ONLINE
|
Sergi Oms
|
Faculty
of Philosophy, University
of Barcelona
|
|
The
epistemic structure of
paradoxes and the Problem of
Change
|
In this paper, we present an
argument that shows that if
something is, apparently, a
paradox, then it is in fact a
paradox. Furthermore, we apply
our findings to a recent
discussion on the so-called
‘Problem of Change’. Throughout
the history of philosophy, many
authors have viewed change as a
paradoxical phenomenon.
Recently, a number of
philosophers have defended that
the Problem of Change is not a
paradox. In the paper, we argue
that the Problem of Change is an
apparent paradox, thereby
establishing that it is a
paradox.
|
|
|
|
|