Budapest, Pázmány P. sétány 1/A
1999. október 4. (hétfő)
12:30
6. em. 654.
Department of Philosophy, Jagiellonian University, Cracow
Outcomes in Branching Space-Time (OBST)
An Analysis of Bell’s Theorem
The framework of branching space-time (BST; cf. Belnap 1992, Synthese 92, pp. 385--434) has recently been extended to allow for the introduction of outcomes of events and the analysis of GHZ theorems. (Kowalski & Placek, forthcoming in Brit. J. Phil. Sci. and Int. J. Theor. Phys.)
In BST, space-time and modality are incorporated in the very structure
of the models, which consist of a pair ,
where
is a non-empty set weakly ordered by
,
which is interpreted as ‘causally accessible from’. Maximal upward directed
subsets of
are called ‘histories’, and proper subsets of histories are called ‘events’.
Two events are called ‘space-like separated’ if neither causally precedes
the other. ‘Atomic outcomes’ of an event
are those parts of the event’s causal future that split in
.
The main result of Kowalski & Placek is that the family of outcomes of an event forms a Boolean algebra. The paper also proves that in GHZ setups, there is always a common cause (CC) in the sense of Reichenbach if directions are held fixed, but that there is no single commom common cause (cf. Hofer-Szabó et al., forthcoming in Brit. J. Phil. Sci.) accounting for the outcomes of incompatible settings.
For an analysis of Bell’s theorem, I assign probabilities to outcomes
by imposing a classical probability measure on the Boolean algebra of the
outcomes of each given event. In the derivation of Bell’s theorem, I use
probability measures of the form ,
,
where the subscript indicates that the result is an outcome of the event
of measuring the spin projections along directions
on the left and
on the right. Probabilities for single results on the left or on the right
are calculated from these measures, allowing us to express correlations
as
.
Since correlations between space-like separated results appear disturbing, it is natural to look for an explanation in terms of a CC located in the results’ common past. The CC’s outcomes divide histories in such a way that actual runs of a correlation experiment are seen as belonging to two or more varieties differentiated by hidden factors. You may think of these hidden factors as restoring the deterministic order. You may also be more modest and require only that the hidden factors restore the causal order, i.e., that in each sub-population, the correlations disappear.
Formally, for space-like separated events
and
with
correlated outcomes
and
, respectively,
a CC is an event
preceding both
and
, such
that for every atomic outcome
of
,
where
is defined on the enlarged probability space.
Now, for any correlated pair
we can construct mathematically an enlarged probability space containing
such a CC. Moreover, for any finite number of correlations we can construct
a single large probability space containing a set of distinct CCs, each
CC taking care of one correlation.
However, in the Bell/Clauser-Horne argument, one wants something more:
one postulates a single common CC accounting for all the correlated outcomes
of ,
,
and
. Given
the standard assumptions of locality and ‘no conspiracy’, which in our
framework take the form
we derive the Bell/CH inequalities, which are empirically violated. Thus, there cannot be a common common cause accounting for the Bell/CH correlations.
Tomasz Placek
néhany cikke (ps-file) itt letölthető: Outcomes in
branching space-time and GHZ-Bell theorems; Stochastic
Outcomes in Branching Space-Time: Analysis of Bell's Theorem; On
the Issue of Joint Probabilities in Interpretations of Bell's Inequalities
1999. október 11. (hétfő)
12:30
6. em. 654.
ELTE, MTA Elméleti Fizikai Kutató
Csoport
ELTE, Tudománytörténet és Tudományfilozófia
Tanszék
Einstein megoldotta az EPR-Bell paradoxont?
Úgy tűnik igen, sőt még egy sereg más problémáját a kvantumelméletnek. "Prizma-modell" néven Arthur Fine 1982-ben egy olyan megoldást javasolt az EPR-Bell problémára, és általában a kvantummechanika lokális-realista interpretációjára, amelyről, mint később ő maga kiderítette, már Einstein is említést tett egy 1936-os cikkében, illetve néhány Rosenhez és Schrödingerhez írt levelében. E megoldás nem kapott különösebb visszhangot, sőt maga Fine sem vette igazán komolyan, hiszen későbbi cikkeiben úgy ír a Bell-tételről, mintha az Einstein-Fine-interpretáció nem is létezne. Ennek oka, hogy tévesen, Fine ezt a megoldást a valóságban végrehajtott kísérletekben használt detektorok nem 100%-os hatásfokával hozta kapcsolatba.
Az előadásban az Einstein-Fine-interpretációt egy új megvilágításban mutatom be. Megmutatom, hogy semmi köze nincs a detektorok hatásfokának sokat diszkutált problémájához. A valóságban elvégzett EPR-Bell kísérletek elemzésével megmutatom, hogy e kísérletek logikai szerkezetüknél fogva teljesen kompatibilisek az Einstein-Fine-interpretációval, amely viszont tökéletesen feloldja az EPR-Bell paradoxont.
Az előadás fóliái és az Aspect-kísérletet modellező, az előadást illusztráló
(PC/DOS/full-screen) program letölhető: //hps.elte.hu/~leszabo/Preprints/einstein.htm
1999. október 18. (hétfő)
12:30
6. em. 654.
Conceivability, Possibility and the Mind-Body Problem
I want to take on the question of what a class of arguments, usually called the Conceivability Arguments, have to say about the mind-body problem. These arguments have two different versions. In one version, considerations of conceivability are taken to support the claim that phenomenal consciousness is not identical, realized by, or supervenient on, physical properties (for example, Kripke 1972, 140-162, Nagel 1974, Robinson 1993, White 1986, Jackson 1998, and Chalmers 1996). According to the other version, there is an explanatory gap between phenomenal and physical levels of description, that does not exist with respect to other higher level descriptions, and that may have metaphysical ramifications. (This argument is formulated by Joseph Levine 1998, although he is himself hesitant to accept the conclusion.) My claim is that these arguments do not succeed in establishing their conclusions. That is because, and I take this to be the primary lesson of the Conceivability Arguments, what they reveal does not have to do with phenomenal consciousness itself, it rather has to do with the nature of phenomenal concepts.
In the paper, I will focus on the most elaborate and sophisticated version
of the Conceivability Argument for dualism. I first provide a general exposition
of the structure of Conceivability Arguments, then I proceed to describe
in greater detail Frank Jackson’s and David Chalmers’ new Conceivability
Argument. Finally I construct a reductio that at the same time reveals
where the arguments went wrong.
1999. október 25. (hétfő)
12:30
6. em. 654.
Our brain and our mind
The neuronal bases of consciousness
(Az előadás magyarul lesz!)
1. Introduction
1.1. Definition of awareness & consciousness for the non-philosopher
1.2. "Components" of consciousness
1.3. Levels of human consciousness, coma, sleep, awake states
1.4. "Prerequisites" of consciousness
2. Recent results on the brain and mind problem
2.1. Visual consciousness
2.2. Blindsight
2.3. Perception vs. action
2.4. Bistable percepts
2.4.1. Ambiguous figures
2.4.2. Binocular rivalry
2.5. Electrical brain stimulation and conscious behavior
2.6. Subliminal and supraliminal stimulus processing
2.7. Time scale of consciousness
Humans & Monkeys:
2.8. NCC - Neural Correlate of Consciousness
Theories & models
A szeminárium szervezője: Szabó
E. László